China
experienced a turbulent epoch, some 2500 years ago, during what is
called the Warring States Period. For two to three centuries
following the previous collapse of a steadfast and ethical rule—the
Zhou (pronounced “Jo”) Dynasty—chaos governed, as numerous
small states that had once been allied under the Zhou began to fight
among themselves.
For
the Chinese population, the Warring States Period was very
disturbing, because their culture had always valued collective
cooperation, but now their civilization seemed to be disintegrating.
Those were distressing times.
Over
a period of a couple of centuries during that warring period, a
number of teachers and philosophers came to the fore and offered
their analyses of the plight, along with their counsel about how to
get things back on track and foster once again a moral society that
valued unity. Out of this struggle came the teachings of several
Chinese sages—the most famous today being Confucius.
As
the conflicts wore on, without peace, other philosophers came into
prominence and offered their
ideas for how to get back on track. Some of them were Mencius, Mozi,
Lauzi, Zhunzi, Zhuangzu, Zon Yau, Sunzi, and Han Fei. Many of them
formed their own school, whose students later carried on the
doctrines of the masters. This process was very similar to the
assorted philosophical schools of ancient Greece—and in fact, at
about the same time period.
Coming from divergent backgrounds and
at different times during the Warring States Period, the teachings of
the various philosophers often clashed. Had one of them—say
Confucius—put forth a suggestion early on, which ended the ongoing
conflicts, we may never have had the alternative and sundry ideas the
other teachers offered. As a result, we have a wide variety of rich
philosophical doctrines—each of which conflicts with and/or
supplements the others in various ways.
I will focus here on two of these
sages, Mencius and Zhunzi, who seem to have reached diametrically
opposed conclusions on human nature. As the Warring States conflicts
persisted, many people began to wonder about the essential qualities
of human nature, and whether those qualities are moral or not. The
core question: Is human nature good or bad? Are we basically virtuous
or harmful creatures? Are we born as benign beings or as evil
individuals? Thus, if the first case is true, do we try to encourage
and promote our natural goodness or, in second case, purge ourselves
of our wickedness?
Mencius took the position that we are
inherently good—we're born innocent and our job is to nurture those
sprouts of goodness, in order to come to realize our full potential
as honorable people. Zhunzi took the opposite view: that human nature
is basically bad—we're born as pernicious people and our job is to
learn to purge ourselves of this baleful behavior. Life is a constant
struggle to overcome that devilish trait of ours, Zhunzi maintained.
It's fascinating that both Mencius and
Zhunzi, although they seem to be diametrically opposed, considered
themselves to be pupils of Confucius. They both agreed that Chinese
society must get back on the track of peace and order, but viewed
humans as starting from opposing places. I won't try here to delve
any deeper into the teachings of these two sages or explain their
divergent doctrines. I'm sure that interminable debates could chew on
this issue and never reach an agreed explanation, since the topic
remains relevant and controversial, 2500 years later.
This kind of contention between
scholars is not unique to Chinese philosophy. Western theologians
have similarly disagreed. For example, within Christianity there is
an analogous type of disagreement—between the Catholic doctrine of
original sin and the Quaker concept of “that of God” within every
person.
This question of the basic quality of
human nature is a philosophical query—one that is as relevant today
as it was three millennia ago. I find it fascinating that most all
questions of science—unlike philosophy—get slowly, step-by-step,
answered. Is the Earth at the center of the universe or not? Is there
a “cure” for cancer? We may not know the answers at any given
point in time, but the inevitable advancement of scientific knowledge
will most likely one day offer an answer. Philosophical questions,
however, often have no final answer. Are we innately good or
bad? Tune in next century for the ongoing debate.
No comments:
Post a Comment